Wednesday, April 25, 2018

Due Friday, April 25th - “Existentialism Is a Humanism” By Jean-Paul Sartre

Please read the following essay on Existentialism and comment in this blog space using evidence from the essay in your response.

Three Stages of Existentialism

Humans in Anguish:  "The man who involves himself and who realizes that he is not only the person he chooses to be, but also a law-maker who is, at the same time, choosing all mankind as well as himself, cannot help escape the feeling of his total and deep responsibility.  Of course there are many people who are not anxious; but we claim they are hiding their anxiety, that they are fleeing from it....Anguish is evident, even when it conceals itself."

Humans in Forlornness:  "When we speak of forlornness, we mean only that God does not exist and that we have to face all the consequences of this....The existentialist thinks it very distressing that God does not exist, because all possibility of finding values in a heaven of ideas disappears along with Him; there can no longer an a priori Good, since there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it.  Nowhere is it written that the Good exists, that we must be honest, that we must not lie; because the fact is we are on a plane where there are only men....Neither within him or without does man find anything to cling to.  He can't start making excuses for himself.


Humans in Despair:  "As for despair, the term has a very simple meaning.  It means that we shall confine ourselves to reckoning only with what depends upon our will, or on the ensemble of probabilities which make our action possible....No God, no scheme, can adapt the world and its possibilities to my will."

“Existentialism Is a Humanism”
By Jean-Paul Sartre


Written: Lecture given in 1946
Source: Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre, ed. Walter Kaufman, Meridian Publishing Company, 1989;
First Published: World Publishing Company in 1956;
Translator: Philip Mairet;

My purpose here is to offer a defense of existentialism against several reproaches that have been laid against it.

First, it has been reproached as an invitation to people to dwell in quietism of despair. For if every way to a solution is barred, one would have to regard any action in this world as entirely ineffective, and one would arrive finally at a contemplative philosophy. Moreover, since contemplation is a luxury, this would be only another bourgeois philosophy. This is, especially, the reproach made by the Communists.

From another quarter we are reproached for having underlined all that is ignominious in the human situation, for depicting what is mean, sordid or base to the neglect of certain things that possess charm and beauty and belong to the brighter side of human nature: for example, according to the Catholic critic, Mlle. Mercier, we forget how an infant smiles. Both from this side and from the other we are also reproached for leaving out of account the solidarity of mankind and considering man in isolation. And this, say the Communists, is because we base our doctrine upon pure subjectivity – upon the Cartesian “I think”: which is the moment in which solitary man attains to himself; a position from which it is impossible to regain solidarity with other men who exist outside of the self. The ego cannot reach them through the cogito.

From the Christian side, we are reproached as people who deny the reality and seriousness of human affairs. For since we ignore the commandments of God and all values prescribed as eternal, nothing remains but what is strictly voluntary. Everyone can do what he likes, and will be incapable, from such a point of view, of condemning either the point of view or the action of anyone else.

It is to these various reproaches that I shall endeavour to reply today; that is why I have entitled this brief exposition “Existentialism is a Humanism.” Many may be surprised at the mention of humanism in this connection, but we shall try to see in what sense we understand it. In any case, we can begin by saying that existentialism, in our sense of the word, is a doctrine that does render human life possible; a doctrine, also, which affirms that every truth and every action imply both an environment and a human subjectivity. The essential charge laid against us is, of course, that of over-emphasis upon the evil side of human life. I have lately been told of a lady who, whenever she lets slip a vulgar expression in a moment of nervousness, excuses herself by exclaiming, “I believe I am becoming an existentialist.” So it appears that ugliness is being identified with existentialism. That is why some people say we are “naturalistic,” and if we are, it is strange to see how much we scandalise and horrify them, for no one seems to be much frightened or humiliated nowadays by what is properly called naturalism. Those who can quite well keep down a novel by Zola such as La Terre are sickened as soon as they read an existentialist novel. Those who appeal to the wisdom of the people – which is a sad wisdom – find ours sadder still. And yet, what could be more disillusioned than such sayings as “Charity begins at home” or “Promote a rogue and he’ll sue you for damage, knock him down and he’ll do you homage”? We all know how many common sayings can be quoted to this effect, and they all mean much the same – that you must not oppose the powers that be; that you must not fight against superior force; must not meddle in matters that are above your station. Or that any action not in accordance with some tradition is mere romanticism; or that any undertaking which has not the support of proven experience is foredoomed to frustration; and that since experience has shown men to be invariably inclined to evil, there must be firm rules to restrain them, otherwise we shall have anarchy. It is, however, the people who are forever mouthing these dismal proverbs and, whenever they are told of some more or less repulsive action, say “How like human nature!” – it is these very people, always harping upon realism, who complain that existentialism is too gloomy a view of things. Indeed their excessive protests make me suspect that what is annoying them is not so much our pessimism, but, much more likely, our optimism. For at bottom, what is alarming in the doctrine that I am about to try to explain to you is – is it not? – that it confronts man with a possibility of choice. To verify this, let us review the whole question upon the strictly philosophic level. What, then, is this that we call existentialism?

Most of those who are making use of this word would be highly confused if required to explain its meaning. For since it has become fashionable, people cheerfully declare that this musician or that painter is “existentialist.” A columnist in Clartes signs himself “The Existentialist,” and, indeed, the word is now so loosely applied to so many things that it no longer means anything at all. It would appear that, for the lack of any novel doctrine such as that of surrealism, all those who are eager to join in the latest scandal or movement now seize upon this philosophy in which, however, they can find nothing to their purpose. For in truth this is of all teachings the least scandalous and the most austere: it is intended strictly for technicians and philosophers. All the same, it can easily be defined.

The question is only complicated because there are two kinds of existentialists. There are, on the one hand, the Christians, amongst whom I shall name Jaspers and Gabriel Marcel, both professed Catholics; and on the other the existential atheists, amongst whom we must place Heidegger as well as the French existentialists and myself. What they have in common is simply the fact that they believe that existence comes before essence – or, if you will, that we must begin from the subjective. What exactly do we mean by that?

If one considers an article of manufacture as, for example, a book or a paper-knife – one sees that it has been made by an artisan who had a conception of it; and he has paid attention, equally, to the conception of a paper-knife and to the pre-existent technique of production which is a part of that conception and is, at bottom, a formula. Thus the paper-knife is at the same time an article producible in a certain manner and one which, on the other hand, serves a definite purpose, for one cannot suppose that a man would produce a paper-knife without knowing what it was for. Let us say, then, of the paperknife that its essence – that is to say the sum of the formulae and the qualities which made its production and its definition possible – precedes its existence. The presence of such-and-such a paper-knife or book is thus determined before my eyes. Here, then, we are viewing the world from a technical standpoint, and we can say that production precedes existence.

When we think of God as the creator, we are thinking of him, most of the time, as a supernal artisan. Whatever doctrine we may be considering, whether it be a doctrine like that of Descartes, or of Leibnitz himself, we always imply that the will follows, more or less, from the understanding or at least accompanies it, so that when God creates he knows precisely what he is creating. Thus, the conception of man in the mind of God is comparable to that of the paper-knife in the mind of the artisan: God makes man according to a procedure and a conception, exactly as the artisan manufactures a paper-knife, following a definition and a formula. Thus each individual man is the realisation of a certain conception which dwells in the divine understanding. In the philosophic atheism of the eighteenth century, the notion of God is suppressed, but not, for all that, the idea that essence is prior to existence; something of that idea we still find everywhere, in Diderot, in Voltaire and even in Kant. Man possesses a human nature; that “human nature,” which is the conception of human being, is found in every man; which means that each man is a particular example of a universal conception, the conception of Man. In Kant, this universality goes so far that the wild man of the woods, man in the state of nature and the bourgeois are all contained in the same definition and have the same fundamental qualities. Here again, the essence of man precedes that historic existence which we confront in experience.

Atheistic existentialism, of which I am a representative, declares with greater consistency that if God does not exist there is at least one being whose existence comes before its essence, a being which exists before it can be defined by any conception of it. That being is man or, as Heidegger has it, the human reality. What do we mean by saying that existence precedes essence? We mean that man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world – and defines himself afterwards. If man as the existentialist sees him is not definable, it is because to begin with he is nothing. He will not be anything until later, and then he will be what he makes of himself. Thus, there is no human nature, because there is no God to have a conception of it. Man simply is. Not that he is simply what he conceives himself to be, but he is what he wills, and as he conceives himself after already existing – as he wills to be after that leap towards existence. Man is nothing else but that which he makes of himself. That is the first principle of existentialism. And this is what people call its “subjectivity,” using the word as a reproach against us. But what do we mean to say by this, but that man is of a greater dignity than a stone or a table? For we mean to say that man primarily exists – that man is, before all else, something which propels itself towards a future and is aware that it is doing so. Man is, indeed, a project which possesses a subjective life, instead of being a kind of moss, or a fungus or a cauliflower. Before that projection of the self nothing exists; not even in the heaven of intelligence: man will only attain existence when he is what he purposes to be. Not, however, what he may wish to be. For what we usually understand by wishing or willing is a conscious decision taken – much more often than not – after we have made ourselves what we are. I may wish to join a party, to write a book or to marry – but in such a case what is usually called my will is probably a manifestation of a prior and more spontaneous decision. If, however, it is true that existence is prior to essence, man is responsible for what he is. Thus, the first effect of existentialism is that it puts every man in possession of himself as he is, and places the entire responsibility for his existence squarely upon his own shoulders. And, when we say that man is responsible for himself, we do not mean that he is responsible only for his own individuality, but that he is responsible for all men. The word “subjectivism” is to be understood in two senses, and our adversaries play upon only one of them. Subjectivism means, on the one hand, the freedom of the individual subject and, on the other, that man cannot pass beyond human subjectivity. It is the latter which is the deeper meaning of existentialism. When we say that man chooses himself, we do mean that every one of us must choose himself; but by that we also mean that in choosing for himself he chooses for all men. For in effect, of all the actions a man may take in order to create himself as he wills to be, there is not one which is not creative, at the same time, of an image of man such as he believes he ought to be. To choose between this or that is at the same time to affirm the value of that which is chosen; for we are unable ever to choose the worse. What we choose is always the better; and nothing can be better for us unless it is better for all. If, moreover, existence precedes essence and we will to exist at the same time as we fashion our image, that image is valid for all and for the entire epoch in which we find ourselves. Our responsibility is thus much greater than we had supposed, for it concerns mankind as a whole. If I am a worker, for instance, I may choose to join a Christian rather than a Communist trade union. And if, by that membership, I choose to signify that resignation is, after all, the attitude that best becomes a man, that man’s kingdom is not upon this earth, I do not commit myself alone to that view. Resignation is my will for everyone, and my action is, in consequence, a commitment on behalf of all mankind. Or if, to take a more personal case, I decide to marry and to have children, even though this decision proceeds simply from my situation, from my passion or my desire, I am thereby committing not only myself, but humanity as a whole, to the practice of monogamy. I am thus responsible for myself and for all men, and I am creating a certain image of man as I would have him to be. In fashioning myself I fashion man.

This may enable us to understand what is meant by such terms – perhaps a little grandiloquent – as anguish, abandonment and despair. As you will soon see, it is very simple. First, what do we mean by anguish? – The existentialist frankly states that man is in anguish. His meaning is as follows: When a man commits himself to anything, fully realising that he is not only choosing what he will be, but is thereby at the same time a legislator deciding for the whole of mankind – in such a moment a man cannot escape from the sense of complete and profound responsibility. There are many, indeed, who show no such anxiety. But we affirm that they are merely disguising their anguish or are in flight from it. Certainly, many people think that in what they are doing they commit no one but themselves to anything: and if you ask them, “What would happen if everyone did so?” they shrug their shoulders and reply, “Everyone does not do so.” But in truth, one ought always to ask oneself what would happen if everyone did as one is doing; nor can one escape from that disturbing thought except by a kind of self-deception. The man who lies in self-excuse, by saying “Everyone will not do it” must be ill at ease in his conscience, for the act of lying implies the universal value which it denies. By its very disguise his anguish reveals itself. This is the anguish that Kierkegaard called “the anguish of Abraham.” You know the story: An angel commanded Abraham to sacrifice his son; and obedience was obligatory, if it really was an angel who had appeared and said, “Thou, Abraham, shalt sacrifice thy son.” But anyone in such a case would wonder, first, whether it was indeed an angel and secondly, whether I am really Abraham. Where are the proofs? A certain mad woman who suffered from hallucinations said that people were telephoning to her, and giving her orders. The doctor asked, “But who is it that speaks to you?” She replied: “He says it is God.” And what, indeed, could prove to her that it was God? If an angel appears to me, what is the proof that it is an angel; or, if I hear voices, who can prove that they proceed from heaven and not from hell, or from my own subconsciousness or some pathological condition? Who can prove that they are really addressed to me?

Who, then, can prove that I am the proper person to impose, by my own choice, my conception of man upon mankind? I shall never find any proof whatever; there will be no sign to convince me of it. If a voice speaks to me, it is still I myself who must decide whether the voice is or is not that of an angel. If I regard a certain course of action as good, it is only I who choose to say that it is good and not bad. There is nothing to show that I am Abraham: nevertheless I also am obliged at every instant to perform actions which are examples. Everything happens to every man as though the whole human race had its eyes fixed upon what he is doing and regulated its conduct accordingly. So every man ought to say, “Am I really a man who has the right to act in such a manner that humanity regulates itself by what I do.” If a man does not say that, he is dissembling his anguish. Clearly, the anguish with which we are concerned here is not one that could lead to quietism or inaction. It is anguish pure and simple, of the kind well known to all those who have borne responsibilities. When, for instance, a military leader takes upon himself the responsibility for an attack and sends a number of men to their death, he chooses to do it and at bottom he alone chooses. No doubt under a higher command, but its orders, which are more general, require interpretation by him and upon that interpretation depends the life of ten, fourteen or twenty men. In making the decision, he cannot but feel a certain anguish. All leaders know that anguish. It does not prevent their acting, on the contrary it is the very condition of their action, for the action presupposes that there is a plurality of possibilities, and in choosing one of these, they realize that it has value only because it is chosen. Now it is anguish of that kind which existentialism describes, and moreover, as we shall see, makes explicit through direct responsibility towards other men who are concerned. Far from being a screen which could separate us from action, it is a condition of action itself.

And when we speak of “abandonment” – a favorite word of Heidegger – we only mean to say that God does not exist, and that it is necessary to draw the consequences of his absence right to the end. The existentialist is strongly opposed to a certain type of secular moralism which seeks to suppress God at the least possible expense. Towards 1880, when the French professors endeavoured to formulate a secular morality, they said something like this: God is a useless and costly hypothesis, so we will do without it. However, if we are to have morality, a society and a law-abiding world, it is essential that certain values should be taken seriously; they must have an a priori existence ascribed to them. It must be considered obligatory a priori to be honest, not to lie, not to beat one’s wife, to bring up children and so forth; so we are going to do a little work on this subject, which will enable us to show that these values exist all the same, inscribed in an intelligible heaven although, of course, there is no God. In other words – and this is, I believe, the purport of all that we in France call radicalism – nothing will be changed if God does not exist; we shall rediscover the same norms of honesty, progress and humanity, and we shall have disposed of God as an out-of-date hypothesis which will die away quietly of itself. The existentialist, on the contrary, finds it extremely embarrassing that God does not exist, for there disappears with Him all possibility of finding values in an intelligible heaven. There can no longer be any good a priori, since there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it. It is nowhere written that “the good” exists, that one must be honest or must not lie, since we are now upon the plane where there are only men. Dostoevsky once wrote: “If God did not exist, everything would be permitted”; and that, for existentialism, is the starting point. Everything is indeed permitted if God does not exist, and man is in consequence forlorn, for he cannot find anything to depend upon either within or outside himself. He discovers forthwith, that he is without excuse. For if indeed existence precedes essence, one will never be able to explain one’s action by reference to a given and specific human nature; in other words, there is no determinism – man is free, man is freedom. Nor, on the other hand, if God does not exist, are we provided with any values or commands that could legitimise our behaviour. Thus we have neither behind us, nor before us in a luminous realm of values, any means of justification or excuse. – We are left alone, without excuse. That is what I mean when I say that man is condemned to be free. Condemned, because he did not create himself, yet is nevertheless at liberty, and from the moment that he is thrown into this world he is responsible for everything he does. The existentialist does not believe in the power of passion. He will never regard a grand passion as a destructive torrent upon which a man is swept into certain actions as by fate, and which, therefore, is an excuse for them. He thinks that man is responsible for his passion. Neither will an existentialist think that a man can find help through some sign being vouchsafed upon earth for his orientation: for he thinks that the man himself interprets the sign as he chooses. He thinks that every man, without any support or help whatever, is condemned at every instant to invent man. As Ponge has written in a very fine article, “Man is the future of man.” That is exactly true. Only, if one took this to mean that the future is laid up in Heaven, that God knows what it is, it would be false, for then it would no longer even be a future. If, however, it means that, whatever man may now appear to be, there is a future to be fashioned, a virgin future that awaits him – then it is a true saying. But in the present one is forsaken.

As an example by which you may the better understand this state of abandonment, I will refer to the case of a pupil of mine, who sought me out in the following circumstances. His father was quarrelling with his mother and was also inclined to be a “collaborator”; his elder brother had been killed in the German offensive of 1940 and this young man, with a sentiment somewhat primitive but generous, burned to avenge him. His mother was living alone with him, deeply afflicted by the semi-treason of his father and by the death of her eldest son, and her one consolation was in this young man. But he, at this moment, had the choice between going to England to join the Free French Forces or of staying near his mother and helping her to live. He fully realised that this woman lived only for him and that his disappearance – or perhaps his death – would plunge her into despair. He also realised that, concretely and in fact, every action he performed on his mother’s behalf would be sure of effect in the sense of aiding her to live, whereas anything he did in order to go and fight would be an ambiguous action which might vanish like water into sand and serve no purpose. For instance, to set out for England he would have to wait indefinitely in a Spanish camp on the way through Spain; or, on arriving in England or in Algiers he might be put into an office to fill up forms. Consequently, he found himself confronted by two very different modes of action; the one concrete, immediate, but directed towards only one individual; and the other an action addressed to an end infinitely greater, a national collectivity, but for that very reason ambiguous – and it might be frustrated on the way. At the same time, he was hesitating between two kinds of morality; on the one side the morality of sympathy, of personal devotion and, on the other side, a morality of wider scope but of more debatable validity. He had to choose between those two. What could help him to choose? Could the Christian doctrine? No. Christian doctrine says: Act with charity, love your neighbour, deny yourself for others, choose the way which is hardest, and so forth. But which is the harder road? To whom does one owe the more brotherly love, the patriot or the mother? Which is the more useful aim, the general one of fighting in and for the whole community, or the precise aim of helping one particular person to live? Who can give an answer to that a priori? No one. Nor is it given in any ethical scripture. The Kantian ethic says, Never regard another as a means, but always as an end. Very well; if I remain with my mother, I shall be regarding her as the end and not as a means: but by the same token I am in danger of treating as means those who are fighting on my behalf; and the converse is also true, that if I go to the aid of the combatants I shall be treating them as the end at the risk of treating my mother as a means. If values are uncertain, if they are still too abstract to determine the particular, concrete case under consideration, nothing remains but to trust in our instincts. That is what this young man tried to do; and when I saw him he said, “In the end, it is feeling that counts; the direction in which it is really pushing me is the one I ought to choose. If I feel that I love my mother enough to sacrifice everything else for her – my will to be avenged, all my longings for action and adventure then I stay with her. If, on the contrary, I feel that my love for her is not enough, I go.” But how does one estimate the strength of a feeling? The value of his feeling for his mother was determined precisely by the fact that he was standing by her. I may say that I love a certain friend enough to sacrifice such or such a sum of money for him, but I cannot prove that unless I have done it. I may say, “I love my mother enough to remain with her,” if actually I have remained with her. I can only estimate the strength of this affection if I have performed an action by which it is defined and ratified. But if I then appeal to this affection to justify my action, I find myself drawn into a vicious circle.

Moreover, as Gide has very well said, a sentiment which is play-acting and one which is vital are two things that are hardly distinguishable one from another. To decide that I love my mother by staying beside her, and to play a comedy the upshot of which is that I do so – these are nearly the same thing. In other words, feeling is formed by the deeds that one does; therefore I cannot consult it as a guide to action. And that is to say that I can neither seek within myself for an authentic impulse to action, nor can I expect, from some ethic, formulae that will enable me to act. You may say that the youth did, at least, go to a professor to ask for advice. But if you seek counsel – from a priest, for example you have selected that priest; and at bottom you already knew, more or less, what he would advise. In other words, to choose an adviser is nevertheless to commit oneself by that choice. If you are a Christian, you will say, consult a priest; but there are collaborationists, priests who are resisters and priests who wait for the tide to turn: which will you choose? Had this young man chosen a priest of the resistance, or one of the collaboration, he would have decided beforehand the kind of advice he was to receive. Similarly, in coming to me, he knew what advice I should give him, and I had but one reply to make. You are free, therefore choose, that is to say, invent. No rule of general morality can show you what you ought to do: no signs are vouchsafed in this world. The Catholics will reply, “Oh, but they are!” Very well; still, it is I myself, in every case, who have to interpret the signs. While I was imprisoned, I made the acquaintance of a somewhat remarkable man, a Jesuit, who had become a member of that order in the following manner. In his life he had suffered a succession of rather severe setbacks. His father had died when he was a child, leaving him in poverty, and he had been awarded a free scholarship in a religious institution, where he had been made continually to feel that he was accepted for charity’s sake, and, in consequence, he had been denied several of those distinctions and honours which gratify children. Later, about the age of eighteen, he came to grief in a sentimental affair; and finally, at twenty-two – this was a trifle in itself, but it was the last drop that overflowed his cup – he failed in his military examination. This young man, then, could regard himself as a total failure: it was a sign – but a sign of what? He might have taken refuge in bitterness or despair. But he took it – very cleverly for him – as a sign that he was not intended for secular success, and that only the attainments of religion, those of sanctity and of faith, were accessible to him. He interpreted his record as a message from God, and became a member of the Order. Who can doubt but that this decision as to the meaning of the sign was his, and his alone? One could have drawn quite different conclusions from such a series of reverses – as, for example, that he had better become a carpenter or a revolutionary. For the decipherment of the sign, however, he bears the entire responsibility. That is what “abandonment” implies, that we ourselves decide our being. And with this abandonment goes anguish.

As for “despair,” the meaning of this expression is extremely simple. It merely means that we limit ourselves to a reliance upon that which is within our wills, or within the sum of the probabilities which render our action feasible. Whenever one wills anything, there are always these elements of probability. If I am counting upon a visit from a friend, who may be coming by train or by tram, I presuppose that the train will arrive at the appointed time, or that the tram will not be derailed. I remain in the realm of possibilities; but one does not rely upon any possibilities beyond those that are strictly concerned in one’s action. Beyond the point at which the possibilities under consideration cease to affect my action, I ought to disinterest myself. For there is no God and no prevenient design, which can adapt the world and all its possibilities to my will. When Descartes said, “Conquer yourself rather than the world,” what he meant was, at bottom, the same – that we should act without hope.

Marxists, to whom I have said this, have answered: “Your action is limited, obviously, by your death; but you can rely upon the help of others. That is, you can count both upon what the others are doing to help you elsewhere, as in China and in Russia, and upon what they will do later, after your death, to take up your action and carry it forward to its final accomplishment which will be the revolution. Moreover you must rely upon this; not to do so is immoral.” To this I rejoin, first, that I shall always count upon my comrades-in-arms in the struggle, in so far as they are committed, as I am, to a definite, common cause; and in the unity of a party or a group which I can more or less control – that is, in which I am enrolled as a militant and whose movements at every moment are known to me. In that respect, to rely upon the unity and the will of the party is exactly like my reckoning that the train will run to time or that the tram will not be derailed. But I cannot count upon men whom I do not know, I cannot base my confidence upon human goodness or upon man’s interest in the good of society, seeing that man is free and that there is no human nature which I can take as foundational. I do not know where the Russian revolution will lead. I can admire it and take it as an example in so far as it is evident, today, that the proletariat plays a part in Russia which it has attained in no other nation. But I cannot affirm that this will necessarily lead to the triumph of the proletariat: I must confine myself to what I can see. Nor can I be sure that comrades-in-arms will take up my work after my death and carry it to the maximum perfection, seeing that those men are free agents and will freely decide, tomorrow, what man is then to be. Tomorrow, after my death, some men may decide to establish Fascism, and the others may be so cowardly or so slack as to let them do so. If so, Fascism will then be the truth of man, and so much the worse for us. In reality, things will be such as men have decided they shall be. Does that mean that I should abandon myself to quietism? No. First I ought to commit myself and then act my commitment, according to the time-honoured formula that “one need not hope in order to undertake one’s work.” Nor does this mean that I should not belong to a party, but only that I should be without illusion and that I should do what I can. For instance, if I ask myself “Will the social ideal as such, ever become a reality?” I cannot tell, I only know that whatever may be in my power to make it so, I shall do; beyond that, I can count upon nothing.

Quietism is the attitude of people who say, “let others do what I cannot do.” The doctrine I am presenting before you is precisely the opposite of this, since it declares that there is no reality except in action. It goes further, indeed, and adds, “Man is nothing else but what he purposes, he exists only in so far as he realises himself, he is therefore nothing else but the sum of his actions, nothing else but what his life is.” Hence we can well understand why some people are horrified by our teaching. For many have but one resource to sustain them in their misery, and that is to think, “Circumstances have been against me, I was worthy to be something much better than I have been. I admit I have never had a great love or a great friendship; but that is because I never met a man or a woman who were worthy of it; if I have not written any very good books, it is because I had not the leisure to do so; or, if I have had no children to whom I could devote myself it is because I did not find the man I could have lived with. So there remains within me a wide range of abilities, inclinations and potentialities, unused but perfectly viable, which endow me with a worthiness that could never be inferred from the mere history of my actions.” But in reality and for the existentialist, there is no love apart from the deeds of love; no potentiality of love other than that which is manifested in loving; there is no genius other than that which is expressed in works of art. The genius of Proust is the totality of the works of Proust; the genius of Racine is the series of his tragedies, outside of which there is nothing. Why should we attribute to Racine the capacity to write yet another tragedy when that is precisely what he did not write? In life, a man commits himself, draws his own portrait and there is nothing but that portrait. No doubt this thought may seem comfortless to one who has not made a success of his life. On the other hand, it puts everyone in a position to understand that reality alone is reliable; that dreams, expectations and hopes serve to define a man only as deceptive dreams, abortive hopes, expectations unfulfilled; that is to say, they define him negatively, not positively. Nevertheless, when one says, “You are nothing else but what you live,” it does not imply that an artist is to be judged solely by his works of art, for a thousand other things contribute no less to his definition as a man. What we mean to say is that a man is no other than a series of undertakings, that he is the sum, the organisation, the set of relations that constitute these undertakings.

In the light of all this, what people reproach us with is not, after all, our pessimism, but the sternness of our optimism. If people condemn our works of fiction, in which we describe characters that are base, weak, cowardly and sometimes even frankly evil, it is not only because those characters are base, weak, cowardly or evil. For suppose that, like Zola, we showed that the behaviour of these characters was caused by their heredity, or by the action of their environment upon them, or by determining factors, psychic or organic. People would be reassured, they would say, “You see, that is what we are like, no one can do anything about it.” But the existentialist, when he portrays a coward, shows him as responsible for his cowardice. He is not like that on account of a cowardly heart or lungs or cerebrum, he has not become like that through his physiological organism; he is like that because he has made himself into a coward by actions. There is no such thing as a cowardly temperament. There are nervous temperaments; there is what is called impoverished blood, and there are also rich temperaments. But the man whose blood is poor is not a coward for all that, for what produces cowardice is the act of giving up or giving way; and a temperament is not an action. A coward is defined by the deed that he has done. What people feel obscurely, and with horror, is that the coward as we present him is guilty of being a coward. What people would prefer would be to be born either a coward or a hero. One of the charges most often laid against the Chemins de la Liberté is something like this: “But, after all, these people being so base, how can you make them into heroes?” That objection is really rather comic, for it implies that people are born heroes: and that is, at bottom, what such people would like to think. If you are born cowards, you can be quite content, you can do nothing about it and you will be cowards all your lives whatever you do; and if you are born heroes you can again be quite content; you will be heroes all your lives eating and drinking heroically. Whereas the existentialist says that the coward makes himself cowardly, the hero makes himself heroic; and that there is always a possibility for the coward to give up cowardice and for the hero to stop being a hero. What counts is the total commitment, and it is not by a particular case or particular action that you are committed altogether.

We have now, I think, dealt with a certain number of the reproaches against existentialism. You have seen that it cannot be regarded as a philosophy of quietism since it defines man by his action; nor as a pessimistic description of man, for no doctrine is more optimistic, the destiny of man is placed within himself. Nor is it an attempt to discourage man from action since it tells him that there is no hope except in his action, and that the one thing which permits him to have life is the deed. Upon this level therefore, what we are considering is an ethic of action and self-commitment. However, we are still reproached, upon these few data, for confining man within his individual subjectivity. There again people badly misunderstand us.

Our point of departure is, indeed, the subjectivity of the individual, and that for strictly philosophic reasons. It is not because we are bourgeois, but because we seek to base our teaching upon the truth, and not upon a collection of fine theories, full of hope but lacking real foundations. And at the point of departure there cannot be any other truth than this, I think, therefore I am, which is the absolute truth of consciousness as it attains to itself. Every theory which begins with man, outside of this moment of self-attainment, is a theory which thereby suppresses the truth, for outside of the Cartesian cogito, all objects are no more than probable, and any doctrine of probabilities which is not attached to a truth will crumble into nothing. In order to define the probable one must possess the true. Before there can be any truth whatever, then, there must be an absolute truth, and there is such a truth which is simple, easily attained and within the reach of everybody; it consists in one’s immediate sense of one’s self.

In the second place, this theory alone is compatible with the dignity of man, it is the only one which does not make man into an object. All kinds of materialism lead one to treat every man including oneself as an object – that is, as a set of pre-determined reactions, in no way different from the patterns of qualities and phenomena which constitute a table, or a chair or a stone. Our aim is precisely to establish the human kingdom as a pattern of values in distinction from the material world. But the subjectivity which we thus postulate as the standard of truth is no narrowly individual subjectivism, for as we have demonstrated, it is not only one’s own self that one discovers in the cogito, but those of others too. Contrary to the philosophy of Descartes, contrary to that of Kant, when we say “I think” we are attaining to ourselves in the presence of the other, and we are just as certain of the other as we are of ourselves. Thus the man who discovers himself directly in the cogito also discovers all the others, and discovers them as the condition of his own existence. He recognises that he cannot be anything (in the sense in which one says one is spiritual, or that one is wicked or jealous) unless others recognise him as such. I cannot obtain any truth whatsoever about myself, except through the mediation of another. The other is indispensable to my existence, and equally so to any knowledge I can have of myself. Under these conditions, the intimate discovery of myself is at the same time the revelation of the other as a freedom which confronts mine, and which cannot think or will without doing so either for or against me. Thus, at once, we find ourselves in a world which is, let us say, that of “inter-subjectivity”. It is in this world that man has to decide what he is and what others are.

Furthermore, although it is impossible to find in each and every man a universal essence that can be called human nature, there is nevertheless a human universality of condition. It is not by chance that the thinkers of today are so much more ready to speak of the condition than of the nature of man. By his condition they understand, with more or less clarity, all the limitations which a priori define man’s fundamental situation in the universe. His historical situations are variable: man may be born a slave in a pagan society or may be a feudal baron, or a proletarian. But what never vary are the necessities of being in the world, of having to labor and to die there. These limitations are neither subjective nor objective, or rather there is both a subjective and an objective aspect of them. Objective, because we meet with them everywhere and they are everywhere recognisable: and subjective because they are lived and are nothing if man does not live them – if, that is to say, he does not freely determine himself and his existence in relation to them. And, diverse though man’s purpose may be, at least none of them is wholly foreign to me, since every human purpose presents itself as an attempt either to surpass these limitations, or to widen them, or else to deny or to accommodate oneself to them. Consequently every purpose, however individual it may be, is of universal value. Every purpose, even that of a Chinese, an Indian or a Negro, can be understood by a European. To say it can be understood, means that the European of 1945 may be striving out of a certain situation towards the same limitations in the same way, and that he may reconceive in himself the purpose of the Chinese, of the Indian or the African. In every purpose there is universality, in this sense that every purpose is comprehensible to every man. Not that this or that purpose defines man for ever, but that it may be entertained again and again. There is always some way of understanding an idiot, a child, a primitive man or a foreigner if one has sufficient information. In this sense we may say that there is a human universality, but it is not something given; it is being perpetually made. I make this universality in choosing myself; I also make it by understanding the purpose of any other man, of whatever epoch. This absoluteness of the act of choice does not alter the relativity of each epoch.

What is at the very heart and center of existentialism, is the absolute character of the free commitment, by which every man realises himself in realising a type of humanity – a commitment always understandable, to no matter whom in no matter what epoch – and its bearing upon the relativity of the cultural pattern which may result from such absolute commitment. One must observe equally the relativity of Cartesianism and the absolute character of the Cartesian commitment. In this sense you may say, if you like, that every one of us makes the absolute by breathing, by eating, by sleeping or by behaving in any fashion whatsoever. There is no difference between free being – being as self-committal, as existence choosing its essence – and absolute being. And there is no difference whatever between being as an absolute, temporarily localised that is, localised in history – and universally intelligible being.

This does not completely refute the charge of subjectivism. Indeed that objection appears in several other forms, of which the first is as follows. People say to us, “Then it does not matter what you do,” and they say this in various ways.

First they tax us with anarchy; then they say, “You cannot judge others, for there is no reason for preferring one purpose to another”; finally, they may say, “Everything being merely voluntary in this choice of yours, you give away with one hand what you pretend to gain with the other.” These three are not very serious objections. As to the first, to say that it does not matter what you choose is not correct. In one sense choice is possible, but what is not possible is not to choose. I can always choose, but I must know that if I do not choose, that is still a choice. This, although it may appear merely formal, is of great importance as a limit to fantasy and caprice. For, when I confront a real situation – for example, that I am a sexual being, able to have relations with a being of the other sex and able to have children – I am obliged to choose my attitude to it, and in every respect I bear the responsibility of the choice which, in committing myself, also commits the whole of humanity. Even if my choice is determined by no a priori value whatever, it can have nothing to do with caprice: and if anyone thinks that this is only Gide’s theory of the acte gratuit over again, he has failed to see the enormous difference between this theory and that of Gide. Gide does not know what a situation is, his “act” is one of pure caprice. In our view, on the contrary, man finds himself in an organised situation in which he is himself involved: his choice involves mankind in its entirety, and he cannot avoid choosing. Either he must remain single, or he must marry without having children, or he must marry and have children. In any case, and whichever he may choose, it is impossible for him, in respect of this situation, not to take complete responsibility. Doubtless he chooses without reference to any pre-established value, but it is unjust to tax him with caprice. Rather let us say that the moral choice is comparable to the construction of a work of art.

But here I must at once digress to make it quite clear that we are not propounding an aesthetic morality, for our adversaries are disingenuous enough to reproach us even with that. I mention the work of art only by way of comparison. That being understood, does anyone reproach an artist, when he paints a picture, for not following rules established a priori. Does one ever ask what is the picture that he ought to paint? As everyone knows, there is no pre-defined picture for him to make; the artist applies himself to the composition of a picture, and the picture that ought to be made is precisely that which he will have made. As everyone knows, there are no aesthetic values a priori, but there are values which will appear in due course in the coherence of the picture, in the relation between the will to create and the finished work. No one can tell what the painting of tomorrow will be like; one cannot judge a painting until it is done. What has that to do with morality? We are in the same creative situation. We never speak of a work of art as irresponsible; when we are discussing a canvas by Picasso, we understand very well that the composition became what it is at the time when he was painting it, and that his works are part and parcel of his entire life.

It is the same upon the plane of morality. There is this in common between art and morality, that in both we have to do with creation and invention. We cannot decide a priori what it is that should be done. I think it was made sufficiently clear to you in the case of that student who came to see me, that to whatever ethical system he might appeal, the Kantian or any other, he could find no sort of guidance whatever; he was obliged to invent the law for himself. Certainly we cannot say that this man, in choosing to remain with his mother – that is, in taking sentiment, personal devotion and concrete charity as his moral foundations – would be making an irresponsible choice, nor could we do so if he preferred the sacrifice of going away to England. Man makes himself; he is not found ready-made; he makes himself by the choice of his morality, and he cannot but choose a morality, such is the pressure of circumstances upon him. We define man only in relation to his commitments; it is therefore absurd to reproach us for irresponsibility in our choice.

In the second place, people say to us, “You are unable to judge others.” This is true in one sense and false in another. It is true in this sense, that whenever a man chooses his purpose and his commitment in all clearness and in all sincerity, whatever that purpose may be, it is impossible for him to prefer another. It is true in the sense that we do not believe in progress. Progress implies amelioration; but man is always the same, facing a situation which is always changing, and choice remains always a choice in the situation. The moral problem has not changed since the time when it was a choice between slavery and anti-slavery – from the time of the war of Secession, for example, until the present moment when one chooses between the M.R.P. [Mouvement Republicain Poputaire] and the Communists.

We can judge, nevertheless, for, as I have said, one chooses in view of others, and in view of others one chooses himself. One can judge, first – and perhaps this is not a judgment of value, but it is a logical judgment – that in certain cases choice is founded upon an error, and in others upon the truth. One can judge a man by saying that he deceives himself. Since we have defined the situation of man as one of free choice, without excuse and without help, any man who takes refuge behind the excuse of his passions, or by inventing some deterministic doctrine, is a self-deceiver. One may object: “But why should he not choose to deceive himself?” I reply that it is not for me to judge him morally, but I define his self-deception as an error. Here one cannot avoid pronouncing a judgment of truth. The self-deception is evidently a falsehood, because it is a dissimulation of man’s complete liberty of commitment. Upon this same level, I say that it is also a self-deception if I choose to declare that certain values are incumbent upon me; I am in contradiction with myself if I will these values and at the same time say that they impose themselves upon me. If anyone says to me, “And what if I wish to deceive myself?” I answer, “There is no reason why you should not, but I declare that you are doing so, and that the attitude of strict consistency alone is that of good faith.” Furthermore, I can pronounce a moral judgment. For I declare that freedom, in respect of concrete circumstances, can have no other end and aim but itself; and when once a man has seen that values depend upon himself, in that state of forsakenness he can will only one thing, and that is freedom as the foundation of all values. That does not mean that he wills it in the abstract: it simply means that the actions of men of good faith have, as their ultimate significance, the quest of freedom itself as such. A man who belongs to some communist or revolutionary society wills certain concrete ends, which imply the will to freedom, but that freedom is willed in community. We will freedom for freedom’s sake, in and through particular circumstances. And in thus willing freedom, we discover that it depends entirely upon the freedom of others and that the freedom of others depends upon our own. Obviously, freedom as the definition of a man does not depend upon others, but as soon as there is a commitment, I am obliged to will the liberty of others at the same time as my own. I cannot make liberty my aim unless I make that of others equally my aim. Consequently, when I recognise, as entirely authentic, that man is a being whose existence precedes his essence, and that he is a free being who cannot, in any circumstances, but will his freedom, at the same time I realize that I cannot not will the freedom of others. Thus, in the name of that will to freedom which is implied in freedom itself, I can form judgments upon those who seek to hide from themselves the wholly voluntary nature of their existence and its complete freedom. Those who hide from this total freedom, in a guise of solemnity or with deterministic excuses, I shall call cowards. Others, who try to show that their existence is necessary, when it is merely an accident of the appearance of the human race on earth – I shall call scum. But neither cowards nor scum can be identified except upon the plane of strict authenticity. Thus, although the content of morality is variable, a certain form of this morality is universal. Kant declared that freedom is a will both to itself and to the freedom of others. Agreed: but he thinks that the formal and the universal suffice for the constitution of a morality. We think, on the contrary, that principles that are too abstract break down when we come to defining action. To take once again the case of that student; by what authority, in the name of what golden rule of morality, do you think he could have decided, in perfect peace of mind, either to abandon his mother or to remain with her? There are no means of judging. The content is always concrete, and therefore unpredictable; it has always to be invented. The one thing that counts, is to know whether the invention is made in the name of freedom.

Let us, for example, examine the two following cases, and you will see how far they are similar in spite of their difference. Let us take The Mill on the Floss. We find here a certain young woman, Maggie Tulliver, who is an incarnation of the value of passion and is aware of it. She is in love with a young man, Stephen, who is engaged to another, an insignificant young woman. This Maggie Tulliver, instead of heedlessly seeking her own happiness, chooses in the name of human solidarity to sacrifice herself and to give up the man she loves. On the other hand, La Sanseverina in Stendhal’s Chartreuse de Parme, believing that it is passion which endows man with his real value, would have declared that a grand passion justifies its sacrifices, and must be preferred to the banality of such conjugal love as would unite Stephen to the little goose he was engaged to marry. It is the latter that she would have chosen to sacrifice in realising her own happiness, and, as Stendhal shows, she would also sacrifice herself upon the plane of passion if life made that demand upon her. Here we are facing two clearly opposed moralities; but I claim that they are equivalent, seeing that in both cases the overruling aim is freedom. You can imagine two attitudes exactly similar in effect, in that one girl might prefer, in resignation, to give up her lover while the other preferred, in fulfilment of sexual desire, to ignore the prior engagement of the man she loved; and, externally, these two cases might appear the same as the two we have just cited, while being in fact entirely different. The attitude of La Sanseverina is much nearer to that of Maggie Tulliver than to one of careless greed. Thus, you see, the second objection is at once true and false. One can choose anything, but only if it is upon the plane of free commitment.

The third objection, stated by saying, “You take with one hand what you give with the other,” means, at bottom, “your values are not serious, since you choose them yourselves.” To that I can only say that I am very sorry that it should be so; but if I have excluded God the Father, there must be somebody to invent values. We have to take things as they are. And moreover, to say that we invent values means neither more nor less than this; that there is no sense in life a priori. Life is nothing until it is lived; but it is yours to make sense of, and the value of it is nothing else but the sense that you choose. Therefore, you can see that there is a possibility of creating a human community. I have been reproached for suggesting that existentialism is a form of humanism: people have said to me, “But you have written in your Nausée that the humanists are wrong, you have even ridiculed a certain type of humanism, why do you now go back upon that?” In reality, the word humanism has two very different meanings. One may understand by humanism a theory which upholds man as the end-in-itself and as the supreme value. Humanism in this sense appears, for instance, in Cocteau’s story Round the World in 80 Hours, in which one of the characters declares, because he is flying over mountains in an airplane, “Man is magnificent!” This signifies that although I personally have not built aeroplanes, I have the benefit of those particular inventions and that I personally, being a man, can consider myself responsible for, and honoured by, achievements that are peculiar to some men. It is to assume that we can ascribe value to man according to the most distinguished deeds of certain men. That kind of humanism is absurd, for only the dog or the horse would be in a position to pronounce a general judgment upon man and declare that he is magnificent, which they have never been such fools as to do – at least, not as far as I know. But neither is it admissible that a man should pronounce judgment upon Man. Existentialism dispenses with any judgment of this sort: an existentialist will never take man as the end, since man is still to be determined. And we have no right to believe that humanity is something to which we could set up a cult, after the manner of Auguste Comte. The cult of humanity ends in Comtian humanism, shut-in upon itself, and – this must be said – in Fascism. We do not want a humanism like that.

But there is another sense of the word, of which the fundamental meaning is this: Man is all the time outside of himself: it is in projecting and losing himself beyond himself that he makes man to exist; and, on the other hand, it is by pursuing transcendent aims that he himself is able to exist. Since man is thus self-surpassing, and can grasp objects only in relation to his self-surpassing, he is himself the heart and center of his transcendence. There is no other universe except the human universe, the universe of human subjectivity. This relation of transcendence as constitutive of man (not in the sense that God is transcendent, but in the sense of self-surpassing) with subjectivity (in such a sense that man is not shut up in himself but forever present in a human universe) – it is this that we call existential humanism. This is humanism, because we remind man that there is no legislator but himself; that he himself, thus abandoned, must decide for himself; also because we show that it is not by turning back upon himself, but always by seeking, beyond himself, an aim which is one of liberation or of some particular realisation, that man can realize himself as truly human.

You can see from these few reflections that nothing could be more unjust than the objections people raise against us. Existentialism is nothing else but an attempt to draw the full conclusions from a consistently atheistic position. Its intention is not in the least that of plunging men into despair. And if by despair one means as the Christians do – any attitude of unbelief, the despair of the existentialists is something different. Existentialism is not atheist in the sense that it would exhaust itself in demonstrations of the non-existence of God. It declares, rather, that even if God existed that would make no difference from its point of view. Not that we believe God does exist, but we think that the real problem is not that of His existence; what man needs is to find himself again and to understand that nothing can save him from himself, not even a valid proof of the existence of God. In this sense existentialism is optimistic. It is a doctrine of action, and it is only by self-deception, by confining their own despair with ours that Christians can describe us as without hope.


For further exploration:

“The Myth of Sisyphus”
by Albert Camus




27 comments:

  1. I thought that this was a very interesting piece of writing to read. There was something about reading it that made you think in a different way. That may possibly been because it was translated from a different language, or the way that the paragraphs were split up, but after reading I was left with a sense of self that was much different from before I started. The entire essay revolves, I think, around two central points. “I am responsible for myself and for all men, and I am creating a certain image of man as I would have him to be. In fashioning myself I fashion man” and “Man is nothing else but what he purposes, he exists only in so far as he realizes himself, he is therefore nothing else but the sum of his actions, nothing else but what his life is”. While these two statements seem a little bit juxtapose at first glance, I really believe that they embody what the essay is truly about (or at least they do from what I took away from it). Existentialism is based on the fact that man lives only as an individual and is entirely free in all that he does. A man is only responsible for himself, and in the eyes of an existentialist, self consists of all mankind. When a man does something for himself, he is choosing to do something for all mankind. Therefore, whatever a man chooses to do, he chooses to do for the good and benefit of mankind. In a way, when a man chooses to do anything, he is doing it as he would imagine a “perfect man” would do. I think that a lot of teens have this idea in their head that anything they do is universally right, and everyone else should do as they do. However, I think that this idealism has turned much more into selfishness and has turned into people acting arrogantly or irresponsibly. But in contrast, civilization has only created those terms because they need a way to be able to separate and divide people. I don’t think this is done with poor intentions, but I think it is done because everything needs to have a label, because in reality, people do not have total freedom. If every person on earth were extreme existentialists, then the entire concept of civilization would go to the wind, and it would turn into a world where the basis is every man for himself. But then again, maybe this wouldn’t happen because “the world [could become] so loosely applied to so many things that it no longer means anything at all”. In a way labels drive our society. And the label Existentialist is just another way of dividing and placing people into groups. Overall I thought that this was a very through provoking essay to read, and I look forward to the conversations that follow in class. :)

    ReplyDelete
  2. I think one of the most interesting things about this essay was the idea that people have control and are the "heart and center of [their] transcendence." I found this surprising, if you will, because usually the "existential" conversations I've had with people focus on how small we really are in the universe, that there is no obvious point or reason as to why we are here, etc. and that often results in me freaking out because a complete lack of control is terrifying. The idea that humans are able to grasp next to anything so long as they push themselves was a comforting thought for me. I also liked the discussion of humanism which, of course, reminded me of the humanism movement in the 1500s. People were finally able to read and interpret things for themselves instead of someone of higher power doing it for them. So just like this essay is saying we have control once we're aware of our own capability, that's how it worked out for those involved in the Enlightenment/Humanism era. And I think, like Maddy said, it will be interesting to explore how labels and personal needs control the way we live.

    ReplyDelete
  3. So my head really hurt after reading this essay, but it hurt in a good way, I guess. I had to look up a Crash Course video to make sure I understood some basic elements of Existentialism, but now I think I have the main idea. I’ve never really thought about freewill, predetermination, or essence, but this essay made me think a lot about it. The idea that “Existence comes before essence” makes sense to me, and I think, although I’ve never really articulated it, I agree with this sentiment. The part that I don’t agree with, or maybe I just don't understand it fully, is the idea that man “is responsible only for his own individuality, [and] that he is responsible for all men”. I think that everyone has an effect on other people, but when Sartre started arguing that “action is, in consequence, a commitment on behalf of all mankind” and that in every personal choice, you are promoting the same choice for everyone else, I started to disagree. I don’t believe that “nothing can be better for us unless it is better for all”. In his example, I think he’s saying that if one was to decide to have children, it means that the best choice for everyone is to have children (Am I understanding this correctly?!). I don’t think this is the case at all. It could make total sense for one person to have children, and it would make total sense for someone else to choose not to have children. So what exactly does he mean by this?
    As Sartre argues that we are so free that it’s terrifying, he also claims that “to choose an adviser is nevertheless to commit oneself by that choice”. To find order and meaning in authority is the way in which people try to make sense of this meaningless world. Therefore, when choosing to have your freewill be influenced by an adviser (Authority, society, religion etc), then you are committing yourself to their free will. To Sartre, this isn’t living authentically.
    Here is the link to the Crash Course I watched on Existentialism if it might help others :)
    https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=YaDvRdLMkHs
    Sosha

    ReplyDelete
  4. The principles of existentialism reading made me think about each principle Sartre described, comparing them with my own experiences and trying to figure out if I agreed with what he was saying. For the most part, it made sense to me and the clarity of the first part of The Stranger further cemented the ideas that I had taken from the speech. The biggest takeaway I got from the The Stranger was the deliberate nature of every action taken by the narrator. For example, on page 8, the lines “he offered to bring me a cup of coffee with milk. I like milk in my coffee, so I said yes”, show the exact thought process of the speaker while relaying a simple event. It may not seem to matter very much, but he made an extremely conscious decision. In addition, I thought how the speaker decided not to see his mother’s body was an example of a human in anguish. After the caretaker questions his choice, the speaker says “ I was embarrassed because I felt I shouldn’t have said that” (6). Even though he feels pressured a bit to see his mother, the speaker feels like he doesn’t think a son should be forced to look upon the corpse of their mother, and so he stands by this decision. In this moment, the speaker is in the position of all sons mourning their mother and makes a conscious choice based on his values and his ideas. In addition, I thought this action connected to the part of the speech which Sartre says that whatever the decision made by the individual, it is always the correct decision and we will never know what could have been the outcome had the person chosen differently. The speaker in The Stranger doesn’t seem to be too concerned about the past choices he made because it is clear in every step why he acted however he did. While the speech was a bit more complex to understand, I can see why The Stranger does a good job of putting the principles of Existentialism into the grasp of the reader

    ReplyDelete
  5. “The existentialist, on the contrary, finds it extremely embarrassing that God does not exist, for there disappears with Him all possibility of finding values in an intelligible heaven. There can no longer be any good a priori, since there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it. It is nowhere written that “the good” exists, that one must be honest or must not lie, since we are now upon the plane where there are only men. Dostoevsky once wrote: “If God did not exist, everything would be permitted”; and that, for existentialism, is the starting point. Everything is indeed permitted if God does not exist, and man is in consequence forlorn, for he cannot find anything to depend upon either within or outside himself.”
    I have never believed that there is any moral authority or rules outside our own minds, and that the ones we see around us are simply imposed on the real world by humanity. However the impossibility of “ finding values in an intelligible heaven” has never made me forlorn or been embarrassing. In fact the existence of moral rules outside of ourselves is not only unnecessary, but terrifying. The idea that there is an incorrect way to think or act or live your life, the idea that you are judged by an unknowable set of rules imposed by an unknowable being to scrutinize whether you are worth anything or not. It's like being in a test in a different language your entire life, it's stressing, its enslaving. I’d rather live in a world with no moral rules from the cosmos, where I am able to live and act according to no rules but our own and checked by no judge but ourselves. Does this mean I am an anarchist and think humans should act however we want and rape and murder the night away with no guilt. No. There is no world of morals outside ourselves but there is within. We feel guilt, we feel shame, we believe that we should do good and make ourselves happy. We our the gods that create our own morals and values to live by and we are the ones who judge ourselves for not living up to those morals. Morals, good, evil, don’t exist but they our still real, they come from our minds and shape the society around us to live up to them, like a picture being projected on a blank wall. There are no morals outside of us, the existence of moral greys and contradictions is testament to that, but we act on the morals we believe in and that makes them real enough, for us at least. And the beauty of this is that each of us can be different, each of us can believe different things that we know are true, nothing we think is wrong and we are all able to exist in a world we can understand in a different ways, we can each learn different life lessons and develop different thoughts, even if they contradict.There is no wrong answer, and while that means that tyrants and murderers are as morally validated and nuns and altruists, as there is no validation to be had, and the only thing that makes them monsters is that there morals are so estranged from our own, we can still believe them to be monsters and act on that and be right. And even if our concept of what is right is as true as a bigots or a criminals, it's still ours and our worlds operate by it and what it means to us is all that will ever matter (because nothing matters). We are free to live in a godless, meaningless, moral less universe, and that makes me happy.

    ReplyDelete
  6. Like Sosha, after reading this essay I was pretty confused. Nonetheless, I understood that man is responsible for his own actions and that “the destiny of man is placed within himself.” What I found fascinating about this philosophy was that it focuses on the idea that our existence comes before our essence, or who we become through the way we live. I believe that everyone lives their life according to who they think they are, or else they change it to adhere to their true selves. I think that Rene Descartes famous statement, “I think, therefore I am,” which was brought up in the essay is the absolute truth of consciousness and illustrates what it is to exist. I also found the quote used in the essay by Dostoevsky interesting. He stated, “If God did not exist, everything would be permitted” which gave me another perspective on religion. I think that without some outside, untouchable force, whether it be a God or something else, people would not find anything to depend upon, and therefore anything and everything would be allowed to happen, but I think that any meaning your life has is given to it by oneself or one’s own actions. Anyways, this might not make a lot of sense, but I think that thinking about different philosophies or theories such as this is very fascinating. I also agree with Maddy that it is interesting how much the labeling of others drives our society.

    ReplyDelete
  7. I think my favorite lines from this were “Thus each individual man is the realisation of a certain conception which dwells in the divine understanding.” and “If man as the existentialist sees him is not definable, it is because to begin with he is nothing. He will not be anything until later, and then he will be what he makes of himself. Thus, there is no human nature, because there is no God to have a conception of it.” I never knew that existentialism would have to do with freewill, essence, or anything spiritual but this changed my view completely as it showed existentialism to be a human divinity driven concept. Much like Katie said, whenever I thought of existentialism it was far more of a nihilistic view, that our human lives are miniscule and meaningless in the grand scheme of existence but this view of existentialism is far more comforting as it focused on the amount of control that each individual has over their own existence. Control is something that people, including myself, can struggle their entire lives trying to find in one way or another. Some people look to something or someone to control for them, such as a god or toxic relationships, but this point of view on humans puts control completely in peoples hands. Not only did this show the control all people have but also the ability to create, an almost god like ability. We as humans can think and create anything. Our minds and actions are not at the will of something else emparting their creations on us but they come along with our existence. Wow wow wow wow.

    ReplyDelete
  8. Like Julia and Sosha, I was confused after reading this. I also agree with Katie and Aiden; when I thought of existentialism,I thought of meaningless of life and nihilism. I had not considered that it was about controlling one's own destiny, which is an idea that I like and agree with. I understood when the author spoke about humans being responsible for their own actions, and making their own decisions, however I did not completely follow when he wrote about there not being such a thing as "good". I think I understood what he was trying to get at, but I am still confused about the reasoning behind that, because even without religion and clear rules for good vs. evil, I think that good and bad are still concepts that exist. I was also confused by what he meant when he said that "action is, in consequence, a commitment on behalf of all mankind". I understood it to mean that when one makes a choice, it is the choice he believes all humans should make, but I may be interpreting that completely wrong. Despite my confusion, I did enjoy thinking about all of this.

    ReplyDelete
  9. This comment has been removed by the author.

    ReplyDelete
  10. I haven't had much experience or knowledge of existentialism and, like a few others, I struggled to read this essay not only because of its length but because of the complex ideas within. I watched Sosha's crash course and it definitely helped me understand some more but at the same time, the essay was a lot to handle. Like Katie, whenever I did have conversations around existentialism it was always about being miniscule within an infinite universe and not understanding why we exist or why we do the things we do. I too found it interesting that the essay talked about more than that, it mentioned people having control and free will of their "transcendence." I'm not comfortable with a lack of control so I found it (the belief) comforting that we are capable of seizing something after putting in the effort. Also, I liked gaining a broader perspective on humanism and the idea that humans can think, act, and understand on their own without relying on something unknown or a higher power. It's funny actually because the other day I had to write a letter for a scholarship application for my church but I'm not Catholic (even though I was raised to be) so I had to pretend that I was. It was a pretty uncomfortable experience because well, first off I didn't like lying, but also because I talked about how I had a difficult year and I read the bible and worshiped God as a form of support and healing. Having to say that I felt better after following the scripture and listening to priests who act as messengers for God was a strange thing for me because I like to think logically and while I appreciate feeling spiritual, I don't really enjoy the idea of accepting a higher power without question. Also, like Skylar, I remained confused when it came to good and bad not existing. I think I got the gist of it but I could use more of a verbal explanation.

    ReplyDelete
  11. I never really took notice of the idea of existentialism until reading this poem. Watching the link on Sosha’s blog helped me figure out the essay. I was a little confused at first but I got a few ideas out of it. I realized that humans, don’t have a defined purpose. “ Man is nothing else but that which he makes of himself”, which explains that we have independent lives that are not confined by universal responsibilities. I agree with Domenica and was comforted by the idea of having control over our lives. I thought the example Sartre used to show two different scenarios with the same results was interesting. Two contradicting morals created the same result in the essay. Sartre also didn’t believe in god, which is a logical but bold statement in my opinion. It makes sense because if god existed, then humans would be limited to live a certain way. Their actions would always be predetermined with the understanding of afterlife and god. This was a confusing, difficult read, however I learned a few new ideas through Sartre’s perspective of existentialism.
    Kaby

    ReplyDelete
  12. To be completely honest, I was totally lost when reading this essay. I understood what I think was his main point that people have complete control over their own actions and their own destiny, but he lost me when he started going into the details of his theory. It seemed to me that whenever Sartre drew a conclusion from an example, I didn’t agree, or I didn’t follow his logic. I know he was probably thinking theoretically or metaphorically, but I had a hard time understanding how he came to that conclusion from that example. For example, I didn’t get the part when he said “In fashioning myself I fashion man”. It seemed to me that in fashioning yourself you are only affecting yourself…you might be affecting those around you, or those affected directly from your decision, but I didn’t understand Sartre’s theory that one person making their own personal decisions shapes all of mankind. However, while the details of the essay confused me, I liked thinking about the major idea of controlling your own destiny. I thought it was interesting that while Sartre himself does not believe in God, he allows that belief in the existence of God can coexist with existentialist theory. His firm belief in the need for people to take responsibility for their own lives almost perfectly coincides with some aspects of religion. I think some believers in religion interpret it in a way that is very similar to Sartre’s theory.
    Anna Vrountas

    ReplyDelete
  13. The first time I was exposed to existentialism, my teacher taught it and presented it as a philosophy of not seeing any meaning in life and living an aimless life without hope. That is a more cynical way to look at the philosophy that its “people who deny the reality and seriousness of human affairs. For since we ignore the commandments of God and all values prescribed as eternal, nothing remains but what is strictly voluntary”. However, now I see that this can also be seen as actually understanding the seriousness of human affairs and that it is so serious because it is not all fate, life is a consequence of yourself and your choices. My impression since first being taught this was that existentialism is a philosophy of giving up on the world and losing faith in life itself. But after reading this article, I feel so much more uplifted and actually inspired by existentialism. It can actually be a way to live ones life feeling empowered and holding the capacity to control ones life and always be able to make it better. This complete acception of responsibility is a major mindset to take on and eventhough I personally don’t think that I am currently able to adapt it to my life, I do find there is a lot of potential for freedom in it. Also, an aspect that was mentioned in the article that I found interesting was “when we say that man is responsible for himself, we do not mean that he is responsible only for his own individuality, but that he is responsible for all men”. By feeling that we are all free to do as we want and have complete fredom of action, it’s interesting to think that this total freedom also comes with alot of responsiblity to eachother. We are then responsible to “always to ask oneself what would happen if everyone did as one is doing; nor can one escape from that disturbing thought except by a kind of self-deception. The man who lies in self-excuse, by saying “Everyone will not do it” must be ill at ease in his conscience, for the act of lying implies the universal value which it denies”. Not thinking that there is an outer and superior force guiding our lives, we are left with the responsiblity to not completely act on our own free will which is kind of ironic, but we still must exercise free will, but free will that stops us from a free will that will create chaos.

    ReplyDelete
  14. “that he himself, thus abandoned, must decide for himself; also because we show that it is not by turning back upon himself, but always by seeking, beyond himself, an aim which is one of liberation or of some particular realisation, that man can realize himself as truly human.”

    I learned a bit about existentialism at my church in Sunday school last week by watching “Forrest Gump”. The movie starts with a feather floating randomly in the air, which reminds me the idea of a purposeless, meaningless life and that things happen by chance. It shows a different perspective of existentialism than the one of the essay. But the overall message is still the same- we have to take it upon ourselves to decide. The physical world (reality) is all there is. Be a runner, not a chaser. I don’t agree with anything that Starte says because I wouldn’t necessarily trust myself only to make decisions. I recognize my own weaknesses and I do need help from others.

    ReplyDelete
  15. This comment has been removed by the author.

    ReplyDelete
  16. It was really interesting to read this brief essay on existentialism, as it opened my eyes to different ways of interpreting the human condition. In the past, I’ve associated existentialism with hopelessness, nihilism, and a loss of purpose, but Jean-Paul Sartre completely changed my perspective. Although I am an agnostic, I have always considered religion or the idea of a “sublime” as an imperative part of human existence. Without it, I believe organized civilizations would have never transpired, or at least not as developed as they are at this point in time. Through God, many have discovered purpose and morality. The old Testament, specifically the Ten Commandments, for example, helped establish the social constructs that we still see in the contemporary laws and rules of society. Religion gave people a reason to do good and act morally. Without it, I think the civilizations of ancient times would’ve succumbed to chaos. In every society that has existed and thrived, whether it may have been the Egyptians, Mesopotamians, Qin Dynasty, Roman Empire, Ancient Greece, Aztecs, or any other imaginable congregation of people, religion has been a quintessential part of life. “But he took it – very cleverly for him – as a sign that he was not intended for secular success, and that only the attainments of religion, those of sanctity and of faith, were accessible to him. He interpreted his record as a message from God, and became a member of the Order.” Therefore, I see religion as an important part of existentialism for, through free will, the individual decides what to believe in. This sounds super cliche, but so far, this blog has been my favorite, as it encouraged me to reevaluate and reshape the way I view and interpret the world.

    ReplyDelete
  17. When the book began with “Maman died”, I expected it to have a somber tone and the protagonist to have a mournful response. However, I was completely thrown off guard when it ended up being the complete opposite response with the protagonist reacting indifferently. It initially made me feel that the protagonist, Meursault, was isolated from his feelings and completely lost. He seemed to be unaffected by anything happening to him and acted detached towards not only his emotions, but his interactions with others as well. Even at the news of his own mother’s passing, he does not grief her death, but instead, contemplates the exact day of her death. He writes as an observer instead of a human with emotions, making the book a smooth and enjoyable read. The philosophy of existentialism is often stereotyped as the philosophy of everything being meaningless, due to the fact that there is no “greater purpose”. In the book we see Meursault’s views parallel with this stereotype as he believes everything “doesn’t mean anything” (4). Oddly enough, observing him made me think of this philosophy as refreshing and liberating. He simply responds to the death of his mother as a natural part of the cycle of life stating, “It’s not my fault”, demonstrating the opposite of the classic emotional grieving process people usually go through (2). It is interesting to read the way he lives his life because it exposes the reader to other ways of responding to tragedies and events in our lives. People cannot change events that have happened in their past. They cannot either avoid things that are inevitable, such as death. It is just the way we react to these moments. This outlook could benefit our society, as sometimes humans can be selfish and act based on their own beliefs and emotions, disregarding everyone else’s, which can be harmful. I believe there is balance, however, between completely isolating our emotions from situations and acting from them as the first one can have equally bad consequences than the second. For example, when he uncaringly agrees to his neighbor Raymond to write a letter for his mistress to make her feel guilty for supposably cheating on him, even after he told Meursault that he beats her, it left a bad taste in my mouth.

    As the book goes on, I started to see some cons to the laissez-faire attitude he lives by and that I first admired. He seems to live a normal day-to-day life, going to eat, watching films, and swimming in his free time. It is nice that he lets nothing bother him, but he is also numb to his emotions and everything around him allowing nothing to excite him. It is nice not to worry, but being present and content with the little moments in life is the way to make a person fall in love with it. By just observing and being grateful with the simplest things, he does not seem to be really living, but is instead a robot passing through life with negligence rather than actually living it! It is nice to live consciously as it helps us fall in love with the small, unnoticed things!

    By chapter six, there was finally a breakthrough. Meursault realizes that not only does he not care about anything, and that nothing matters, but that the universe does not care as well.
    When Raymond hands him a gun and he “realizes you could either shoot or not shoot”, he realizes that to the universe it is all the same and that “it amounted to the same thing” (56-57).

    ReplyDelete
  18. This was an eye opening read for me as I have not had much personal experience with the idea of existentialism in my personal life or in a school setting. It was definitely helpful to watch the crash course video on existentialism to get an understanding of what this essay is all about. One of my favorite quotes from the piece which is also a thought provoking question is “Who, then, can prove that I am the proper person to impose, by my own choice, my conception of man upon mankind?” My personal answer to this question is that there are those who need guidance and those who guide in this world. It is necessary for some to be guiders and impose their conception of man upon mankind as those who need guidance would be lost without it. Some people are leaders and other are followers, it is the natural order of things. Also, it is sometimes necessary to impose your opinions on others even when it comes at a cost because sacrifice is necessary for bringing about change. This piece made me reconsider what it meant to be human and think about the true meaning of “the human experience”. I used to think of the human experience as a constant “pursuit of happiness”, but now I feel like happiness is something that we must find within ourselves rather than something that we should expect to be handed to us by society.

    ReplyDelete
  19. I thought that is piece was very interesting, It is different from anything I have read. A quote that I feel as though sums up the entire article is :


    “Existentialism is nothing else than an attempt to draw all the consequences of a coherent atheistic position. It isn’t trying to plunge man into despair at all.”
    This shows the entire argument of Satre’s existentialism, proving that It is not wasting time trying to prove something that we do not know. It shows that no matter what a person believes, we are still responsible for what we have right in front of us, and that will never change. He highlights the ideas of essence, responsibility, arbitrary choices, and making excuses. I really liked this article because I thought it was relatable. Looking at everyday life, it applies to many aspects. I resonated with the quote “Reality alone is what counts.”, because it mirrors the important things we are all facing in life right now. If time is spent arguing about what to believe or not to believe, it is wasting by missing the moment we are in. No matter what you think, it will not change what you are obligated to do.

    ReplyDelete
  20. This essay was a very hard read for me, like many have mentioned it was more the complex ideas more than anything else. I feel that this essay was very thought provoking and even after reading I needed to take a solid thirty minutes just to think about and review how this related to me. The idea that messed with me the most is that we control every choice and we need to take ownership of everything. I don't like this because when I do something wrong or mess up I try to blame it on someone else which helps me to justify my mistake. Obviously not a good thing but a more internal thought process I have than an outward action. I think it is very mature to be able to acknowledge and accept your choices and is extremely admirable. It was also unnerving to read that there is nothing that gives your life meaning, and there is no higher power such as god which was put very bluntly and almost offensively “God is a useless and costly hypothesis, so we will do without it” As someone who is religious I feel that this is a very interesting concept and I have never gotten the chance to think about this before as my family and community are very believing. I thought it was very interesting to think about especially since if there is no higher power would that cause people to act differently as there is no correlation between their actions and an afterlife. I definitely think the extent of existentialism on religion would be something interesting to discuss in class as I realized not all existentialists are atheists. How does one balance worshipping a god but following an ideology that does not?

    ReplyDelete
  21. Although I do wish the vocabulary were a little easier, I also found this read to be really interesting and contain some very substantive points definitely worth thinking over. In particular, the line "it is impossible for [anyone faced with a decision] in respect of this situation, not to take complete responsibility... it is unjust to tax him with caprice" stood out to me. For me, it led to the question of whether or not second chances should still exist. Often, whenever someone makes a mistake, they blame it on either their youth or ignorance and claim that they "didn't know what they were doing until it was too late" and that the person who committed the error "isn't who they really are." In other words, they blame it on a poorly thought-out caprice and emphasize that it is not reflective of their true character. However, by this essay questioning about whether or not caprices really exist and arguing that we should take full responsibility of all our decisions because they are our decisions, it really questions whether that line of reasoning is valid. This made me think back to the novel In the Lake By the Woods that we read over the summer. In it, the main character did participate in a massacre of civilians as a U.S. soldier in the Vietnam war and has his career destroyed because of it. But should the consequences been so harsh? He was just a teenager drafted into a war that he had no interest in participating in, lived under the stifling fear of snipers and hidden bombs for months on end, seen things that no one should ever have to see, gotten caught up in a rush that the rest of his squad also got caught up in- the list goes on. If there was ever someone who deserved a break for his actions, he would be him. But should he have been given a second chance? He did end up killing defenseless civilians- mostly women and children- along with a fellow soldier. For me, it's a heavy question with no definite answer.

    ReplyDelete
  22. This write-up on existentialism was a really elegant and thought-provoking read. I've always been interested in ideas surrounding philosophy and it was interesting to digest this perspective on human cognition. Existentialism, as I see it, is simply a look into the human condition, and the reason for our happiness and our suffering. A belief I've long held is that this theory is a chain. We can ask ourselves questions that branch out further and further until we delve from basic logic into existentialist theory. Why am I studying so intensely for this exam? So that I can get a favorable grade on it. Why do I want a favorable grade on it? So I can pass the class. Why must I pass the class? So my GPA can be high enough for me to secure admission at a desired university. And why do this? For a degree. Why a degree? For a job. Why a job? For money. Why money? For security. Why security? For happiness. Why happiness? Well, that's existentialism. Many people consider existentialism to be a melancholic look on life, but this isn't true, and Jean-Paul Sartre's writing envelopes this thought. We have no way of understanding certain concepts at this point in time, because our current understanding of physics and psychology do not explain the reason for our existence. This is why we look to religion. Whether it be Islam, Christianity, Judaism, Buddhism, Hinduism, or any one of the myriad other religions that people follow, the notion of establishing a sense of meaning that otherwise did not exist, and getting rid of the "anguish, forlornness, and despair" that life entails upon humankind. I believe that existentialism is simply a means to solve this problem of 'not knowing.' It also brings up the question of whether morality is simply a human quality.

    I agree with the others that commented above, that this blog really made me think. Society has developed in such a way that religious labels — Christian, Muslim, Jew, and others — have such strong connotations attached to them. What do they mean, though? If they all follow the same underlying principles, and all are nothing but divergent paths to attain the same goals, we are all far more alike than we are different.

    ReplyDelete
  23. Like Sosha and many others, I was confused on the concept of existentialism after reading this essay. I did not find the essay to be worded in a way that I could fully understand, though I picked up on general ideas from it. A definition for existentialism I found online that made sense to me was, “a philosophical theory or approach that emphasizes the existence of the individual person as a free and responsible agent determining their own development through acts of the will.” So basically after doing some research and reading blog posts from the class I was able to come to terms with the idea. I also tried to find similar terms to existentialism, but there were pretty much no synonyms for the concept that helped me to understand it (and even none on thesaurus.com). I feel like in simple terms, the idea of existentialism is just that people are responsible for their own destinies/ life. I think I agree/ support this theory. I have always been taught by my role models that life is what you make of it, and that you are the one who gets to decide what comes next. Like Skylar said, this idea of destiny being something controllable was very interesting to me. Also, my mom always says that having a good day is a decision. She has explained this to me many times how even if something unfavorable happens, it is your personal choice to deal with it and move on, or let it bother you and ruin your day. This idea never really made sense to me until now, I guess my mom also supports existentialism.
    Cat

    ReplyDelete
  24. This essay was unlike anything I have ever read before, so it was a bit of a difficult read for me. What made it easier is that I had previously read Jean Paul Sartre. I read it in my Dominant Ideas class when we were discussing Existentialism. I think it was the multitude of complex ideas that were talked about is what confused me the most. Existentialism has been a hard concept for me grasp. The idea that nothing matters while everything matters is confusing for me. However, the part about free will and creating your own destiny is what makes sense to me. I think that this is a way that we all should conduct our lives. Sartre's essay made this seemingly simple idea confusing. It is only when I looked up the definition on my own that I was able to understand it better. Existentialism is an idea that does not believe in the power of fate, only free will. I agree with this, but I also think fate is a real thing. I think that some things are meant to happen for a certain reason whether you plan for them or not. If there was a happy medium between free will and living by fate, I think that is where my philosophy on life would stand.
    Colleen

    ReplyDelete
  25. I thought that Camus’ essay was very interesting when viewed both in the lens of the European history that I have been learning this year and in the philosophical and literal lens that we have focused on in this class. It is easy to see where Camus’ critiques of Christian morality would arise in his experience living in France and Algeria during the 20th century: a justice system, the same that convicts Meursault, just a few decades earlier had falsely accused an innocent man in the Dreyfuss affair of treason, meaning to execute or imprison him, based mostly on the fact that he was a Jew (Camus mentions also Zola’s contribution to freeing Dreyfuss—but the remnants of the mob justice that convicted him remained despite the work of investigative reporters like Zola). Throughout Europe’s history, the excuse of Christian morality has been used to justify cruelty; to me, Camus presents a counterpoint, asking what good such a flawed moral system can be and suggesting that we base our actions off of an internal code to try to do right by the world. This idea that all of our actions matter precisely because none of them matter appealed to me because it made me think about my own code; I personally have never been attached to any particular scripture or religious text, and have instead constructed what I hope to be a good system of morality based off of simply trying to do the most good for the people around me. The Existentialist ideas presented in Camus’ essay made me also think about the idea that “a sentiment which is play-acting and one which is vital are two things that are hardly distinguishable one from another.” Does it truly matter if I dislike someone if I nevertheless treat them with kindness and respect? Similarly, if I love someone but treat them poorly, is that worse?

    ReplyDelete
  26. In my opinion, Camus’s essay was very interesting because how it talked about Christianity and its relationship with creating what we call morals. In his essay, Casus critiques Christian morality because how it has promoted bias rulings and promoted cruelty in much of European history. It seems that the moral system we have today is so flawed because we try to right when people’s definition of right is different. Camus uses the existentialist argument that things in life just don’t matter including morals. To him, morals are something non-existentialist hide behind of because there is no other argument to use. So what Camus does is a backtrack where the idea of morality first became popularized which was the Christian church. As someone who is in AP Euro, I know how the church used the argument of morality to misguide people into believing things they said. However, Camus may be making a fair point but I would have to disagree with him. In my opinion, our moral system may be flawed but it is not something that some religion created but an innate human quality. Also by choosing to live in a civilized society the sense of community creates the idea of morality which in turn helps a society be civil. Morals give rules for people live by and honor. If we didn’t things like the bill of rights wouldn’t matter and people’s rights would not be respected. In my opinion, humanism was a way to escape the radical control religion had over Europe, therefore, I believe that existentialism is not the new humanism.

    ReplyDelete